Show simple item record

The Smoke Detector Principle

dc.contributor.authorNesse, Randolph M.en_US
dc.date.accessioned2010-06-01T22:04:01Z
dc.date.available2010-06-01T22:04:01Z
dc.date.issued2001-05en_US
dc.identifier.citationNesse, Randolph M. (2001). "The Smoke Detector Principle." Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 935(1 UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE: THE CONVERGENCE OF NATURAL AND HUMAN SCIENCE ): 75-85. <http://hdl.handle.net/2027.42/75092>en_US
dc.identifier.issn0077-8923en_US
dc.identifier.issn1749-6632en_US
dc.identifier.urihttps://hdl.handle.net/2027.42/75092
dc.identifier.urihttp://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/sites/entrez?cmd=retrieve&db=pubmed&list_uids=11411177&dopt=citationen_US
dc.description.abstractDefenses, such as flight, cough, stress, and anxiety, should theoretically be expressed to a degree that is near the optimum needed to protect against a given threat. Many defenses seem, however, to be expressed too readily or too intensely. Furthermore, there are remarkably few untoward effects from using drugs to dampen defensive responses. A signal detection analysis of defense regulation can help to resolve this apparent paradox. When the cost of expressing an all-or-none defense is low compared to the potential harm it protects against, the optimal system will express many false alarms. Defenses with graded responses are expressed to the optimal degree when the marginal cost equals the marginal benefit, a point that may vary considerably from the intuitive optimum. Models based on these principles show that the overresponsiveness of many defenses is only apparent, but they also suggest that, in specific instances, defenses can often be dampened without compromising fitness. The smoke detector principle is an essential foundation for making decisions about when drugs can be used safely to relieve suffering and block defenses.en_US
dc.format.extent2116987 bytes
dc.format.extent3109 bytes
dc.format.mimetypeapplication/pdf
dc.format.mimetypetext/plain
dc.publisherBlackwell Publishing Ltden_US
dc.rights2001 New York Academy of Sciencesen_US
dc.subject.otherEvolutionen_US
dc.subject.otherNatural Selectionen_US
dc.subject.otherSmoke Detectoren_US
dc.subject.otherDefensesen_US
dc.subject.otherAnxietyen_US
dc.subject.otherStressen_US
dc.subject.otherSignal Detectionen_US
dc.subject.otherPharmacologyen_US
dc.subject.otherDarwinian Medicineen_US
dc.subject.otherMedicineen_US
dc.titleThe Smoke Detector Principleen_US
dc.typeArticleen_US
dc.subject.hlbsecondlevelScience (General)en_US
dc.subject.hlbtoplevelScienceen_US
dc.description.peerreviewedPeer Revieweden_US
dc.contributor.affiliationumDepartment of Psychiatry, The University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan 48104, USAen_US
dc.identifier.pmid11411177en_US
dc.description.bitstreamurlhttp://deepblue.lib.umich.edu/bitstream/2027.42/75092/1/j.1749-6632.2001.tb03472.x.pdf
dc.identifier.doi10.1111/j.1749-6632.2001.tb03472.xen_US
dc.identifier.sourceAnnals of the New York Academy of Sciencesen_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSternbach, R.A. 1963. Congenital insensitivity to pain. Psychol. Bull. 60 ( 3 ): 252 – 264.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference2 Kluger, M.J., Ed. 1979. Fever, its Biology, Evolution, and Function. Princeton University Press. Princeton, NJ.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceDuPont, H.L. &R.B. Hornick. 1973. Adverse effect of Lomotil therapy in shigellosis. JAMA 226: 1525 – 1528.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference4 Schopenhauer, A. & R.J. Hollingdale. 1970. Essays and Aphorisms. Penguin Books. Harmondsworth, England.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference5 Darwin, C. & F. Darwin. 1887. The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin (including an autobiographical chapter), 3rd ed. J. Murray. London.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference6 Wilson, E.O. 1975. Sociobiology. Harvard University Press. Cambridge, MA.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHarvell, C.D. 1990. The ecology and evolution of inducible defenses. Q. Rev. Biol. 65 ( 3 ): 323 – 340.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference8 Edmunds, M. 1974. Defence in Animals. Longman. Harlow, Essex, England.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference9 Janzen, D.H. 1981. Evolutionary physiology of personal defence. In Physiological Ecology: An Evolutionary Approach to Resource Use. C.R. Townsend & P. Calow, Eds.: 145–164. Blackwell. Oxford, England.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference10 Tollrian, R. & C.D. Harvell. 1999. The ecology and evolution of inducible defenses. Princeton University Press. Princeton, N.J.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference11 Mrosovsky, N. 1990. Rheostatis. Oxford University Press. New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference12 Nesse, R.M. & G.C. Williams. 1994. Why We Get Sick: The New Science of Darwinian Medicine. Vintage. New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference13 Cosmides, L. & J. Tooby. 1987. From evolution to behavior: evolutionary psychology as the missing link. In The Latest on the Best: Essays on Evolution and Optimality, J. Dupre, Ed. MIT Press. Cambridge, MA.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceLima, S.L. &L.M. Dill. 1990. Behavioral decisions made under the risk of predation: a review and prospectus. Can. J. Zool. 68: 619 – 640.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference15 Green, D.M. & J.A. Swets. 1966. Signal Detection Theory and Psycho-physics. Wiley. New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference16 Macmillan, N.A. & C.D. Creelman. 1991. Detection Theory: A User's Guide. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge, England.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceNesse, R.M. 1990. Evolutionary explanations of emotions. Hum. Nat. 1 ( 3 ): 261 – 289.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWilliams, G.W. &R.M. Nesse. 1991. The dawn of Darwinian medicine. Q. Rev. Biol. 66 ( 1 ): 1 – 22.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference19 Gramlich, E.M. 1990. A Guide to Benefit-Cost Analysis, 2nd ed. Prentice Hall. Englewood Cliffs, NJ.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHart, B.L. 1990. Behavioral adaptations to pathogens and parasites: five strategies. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 14: 273 – 294.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceYoshimura, J. &W.M. Shields. 1987. Probabilistic optimization of phenotype distributions: a general solution for the effects of uncertainty on natural selection. Evol. Ecol. 1: 125 – 138.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMcEwen, B. &E. Stellar. 1993. Stress and the individual mechanisms leading to disease. Arch. Intern. Med. 153: 2093 – 2101.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference23 Sapolsky, Robert M. 1994. Why Zebras Don't Get Ulcers: A Guide to Stress, Stress-Related Diseases, and Coping. W.H. Freeman. New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMunck, A., et al. 1984. Physiological functions of glucocorticoids in stress and their relation to pharmacological actions. Endocr. Rev. 5 ( 1 ): 25 – 44.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreference25 Nesse, R.M. & E.A. Young. 2000. The evolutionary origins and functions of the stress response. In Encyclopedia of Stress. G. Fink, Ed.: 79–84. Academic Press. San Diego.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMcEwen, B.S. 1998. Protective and damaging effects of stress. N. Engl. J. Med. 338 ( 3 ): 171 – 179.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMarks, I.M. &R.M. Nesse. 1994. Fear and fitness: an evolutionary analysis of anxiety disorders. Ethol. Sociobiol. 15 ( 5–6 ): 247 – 261.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceCurtis, G.C., et al. 1976. “Flooding in vivo” during the circadian phase of minimal cortisol secretion: anxiety and therapeutic success without adrenal cortical activation. Biol. Psychiatry 11: 101 – 107.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKoob, G.F. 1999. Corticotropin-releasing factor, norepinephrine, and stress. Biol. Psychiatry 46 ( 9 ): 1167 – 1180.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePoulton, R., et al. 1998. Evidence for a non-associative model of the acquisition of a fear of heights. Behav. Res. Ther. 36 ( 5 ): 537 – 544.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceCole, J.O. 1988. The drug treatment of anxiety and depression. Med. Clin. N. Am. 72 ( 4 ): 815 – 830.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceNesse, R.M. &K.C. Berridge. 1997. Psychoactive drug use in evolutionary perspective. Science 278: 63 – 66.en_US
dc.owningcollnameInterdisciplinary and Peer-Reviewed


Files in this item

Show simple item record

Remediation of Harmful Language

The University of Michigan Library aims to describe library materials in a way that respects the people and communities who create, use, and are represented in our collections. Report harmful or offensive language in catalog records, finding aids, or elsewhere in our collections anonymously through our metadata feedback form. More information at Remediation of Harmful Language.

Accessibility

If you are unable to use this file in its current format, please select the Contact Us link and we can modify it to make it more accessible to you.