Show simple item record

A CONSIDERATION OF EPISTEMOLOGY IN SYSTEMATIC BIOLOGY, WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO SPECIES

dc.contributor.authorFrost, Darrel R.en_US
dc.contributor.authorKluge, Arnold G.en_US
dc.date.accessioned2010-06-01T20:34:31Z
dc.date.available2010-06-01T20:34:31Z
dc.date.issued1994-09en_US
dc.identifier.citationFrost, Darrel R.; Kluge, Arnold G. (1994). "A CONSIDERATION OF EPISTEMOLOGY IN SYSTEMATIC BIOLOGY, WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO SPECIES." Cladistics 10(3): 259-294. <http://hdl.handle.net/2027.42/73683>en_US
dc.identifier.issn0748-3007en_US
dc.identifier.issn1096-0031en_US
dc.identifier.urihttps://hdl.handle.net/2027.42/73683
dc.description.abstractScience progresses through the development of integrative theories that unify more and more subsidiary theories. Progress in phylogenetic theory comes from mutual reconciliation with the theoretical structure of other branches of evolutionary biology, such as developmental biology, population biology, and population genetics. The notions of species, individuality, and scalar hierarchy are keys to this reconciliation. Conflation of the results and simplifying assumptions of particular discovery operations with the nature of the entities that we search for is a continuing problem in inferential biology. Other problems extend from the fact that scientific discovery operations address sets of entities and sets of interactions, even when the definitions employed by the operations are not rigorous set-definers, but rather generalized descriptive approximations which summarize similarities among the parts of hierarchically more general entities. As an example, in the discovery methods of phylogenetic systematics, organisms (parts of species) are treated as if they are extensions of a set (the lineage considered as a set), rather than as indefinable parts of a particular (the lineage as a system). This simplifying assumption constitutes treating scalar hierarchies as if they are specification hierarchies and, although this may be necessary for scientific progress, it can lead to over-reductionism if applied uncritically. We expect all analytical techniques to fail at some frequency in part because the limits and reality of the entities that scientists attempt to discover do not extend from definitions used in discovery operations, For this reason, all operational definitions in systematics must be patched by theoretical (= process) claims to one degree or another to give us a more complete representation of evolutionary history. In our view, ontology is the result of reconciliation of theoretical expectations and lines of operational evidence (both of “direct” observation and logical techniques). This “consilience of inductions” provides a general picture of the world and illuminates the limitations of particular discovery operations. As our understanding of the lawful nature of the universe improves, we are able to refine the definitions used by our discovery operations. Against the backdrop of the payoffs to evolutionary biology, the various definitions of species are most starkly compared. In cases where tokogeny is not inherently hierarchical, the level of organization chosen as the basic unit that maximizes the explanatory power of phylogenetic hypotheses is the level of Evolutionary Species, which is that of largest integrating lineages, rather than the level of individual organisms. Nevertheless, we recognize that our discovery operations rest on observations of organismal characteristics. The Phylogenetic Species Concept is, at best, the operational equivalent of Evolutionary Species, but may identify parts of Evolutionary Species that are only temporarily isolated. The cost of this kind of error is judged to be small compared with the alternative of recognizing paraphyletic “species” on the basis of potential to recombine. Metaphyly, concerns about exclusiveness of lineages as something more than an analytical issue, and “an escape from species” through operationalism are judged to stem from errors of overreduction.en_US
dc.format.extent1737612 bytes
dc.format.extent3109 bytes
dc.format.mimetypeapplication/pdf
dc.format.mimetypetext/plain
dc.publisherBlackwell Publishing Ltden_US
dc.rights1994 The Willi Hennig Societyen_US
dc.titleA CONSIDERATION OF EPISTEMOLOGY IN SYSTEMATIC BIOLOGY, WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO SPECIESen_US
dc.typeArticleen_US
dc.subject.hlbsecondlevelEcology and Evolutionary Biologyen_US
dc.subject.hlbtoplevelScienceen_US
dc.description.peerreviewedPeer Revieweden_US
dc.contributor.affiliationumCurator, Museum of Zoology, and Professor, Department of Biology, The University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan 48109, U.S.A.en_US
dc.contributor.affiliationotherAssistant Curator, Department of Herpetology and Ichthyology, American Museum of Natural History, Central Park West at 79th Street, New York, New York 10024, U.S.A.en_US
dc.description.bitstreamurlhttp://deepblue.lib.umich.edu/bitstream/2027.42/73683/1/j.1096-0031.1994.tb00178.x.pdf
dc.identifier.doi10.1111/j.1096-0031.1994.tb00178.xen_US
dc.identifier.sourceCladisticsen_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceAckery, P. R. and R. I. Vane-Wright. 1984. Milkweed Butterflies: Their Cladistics and Biology. Cornell Univ. Press, Ithaca, New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceAlberch, P. 1985. Problems with the interpretation of developmental sequences. Syst. Zool., 34: 46 – 58.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceAllard, M. W. and R. L. Honeycutt. 1991. Ribosomal DNA variation within and between species of rodents, with emphasis on the genus Onychomys. Mol. Biol. Evol., 8: 71 – 84.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceArchibald, J. D. 1944. Metataxon concepts and assessing possible ancestry using phylogenetic systematics. Syst. Biol., 43: 27 – 40.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceArnold, E. N. 1981. Estimating phytogenies at low taxonomic levels. Z. Zool. Syst. Evolutionsforsch. 19: 1 – 35.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceAvise, J. C. and R. M. Ball. 1990. Principles of genealogical concordance in species concepts and biological taxonomy. Oxford Surv. Evol. Biol., 7: 45 – 67.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceAx, P. 1985. Stem species and the stem lineage concept. Cladistics, 1: 279 – 287.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBarrett, M., M. J. Donogkue and E. Sober. 1991. Against consensus. Syst. Zool., 40: 486 – 493.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBaum, D. 1992. Phylogenetic species concepts. Trends Ecol. Evol., 7: 1 – 2.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBaum, D. and K. L. Shaw. 1995. Exclusivity, coalescence and the genealogical species. In P. C. Hoch, A. G. Stevenson and B. A. Schaal, ( eds ), Experimental and molecular approaches to plant biosystematics. Monogr. Syst., Missouri Botanical Garden, St. Louis, In press.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBaverstock, P. R., C. H. S. Watts and S. R. Cole. 1977. Electrophoretic comparisons between allopatric populations of five Australian pseudomyine rodents (Muridae). Aust. J. Biol. Sci., 30: 471 – 485.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBoyd, R. 1991. Confirmation, semantics, and the interpretation of scientific theories: Introductory essay. In Boyd, R., P. Gasper and J. D. Trout ( eds ). The Philosophy of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 3 – 35.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBoyd, R., P. Gasper and J. D. Trout ( eds ). 1991. The Philosophy of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBrady, R. H. 1983. Parsimony, hierarchy, and biological implications. In Platnick, N. I. and V. A. Funk, ( eds ), Advances in Cladistics, vol. 2. Columbia Univ. Press, New York, pp. 49 – 60.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBrooks, D. R. and E. O. Wiley. 1985. Theories and methods in different approaches to phylogenetic systematics. Cladistics, 1: 1 – 11.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBrooks, D. R. and E. O. Wiley. 1986. Evolution as Entropy: Toward a Unified Theory of Biology. Univ. Chicago Press, Chicago, Illinois.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBuck, R. C. and D. L. Hull. 1966. The logical structure of the Linnaean hierarchy. Syst. Zool. 15: 97 – 111.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceButts, R. E. ( ed. ). 1989. William Whewell's theory of scientific method. Revised edition. Hackett Publ. Co., Inc., Indianapolis.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceCampbell. J. A. and D. R. Frost. 1993. Anguid lizards of the genus Abronia: Revisionary notes, descriptions of four new species, a phylogenetic analysis, and key. Ball. Am. Mus. Nat. Hist., 216: 1 – 121.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceCarnap, R. 1956. Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. In Meaning and Necessity. Univ. Chicago Press. Reprinted in Boyd, R., P. Gasper and J. D. Trout, (eds), 1991, The Philosophy of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 85–97.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceCracraft, J. 1983. Species concepts and speciation analysis. Current Ornithol., 1: 159 – 187.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceCracraft J. 1987. Species concepts and the ontology of evolution. Biol. Philos., 2: 329 – 346.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceCracraft, J. 1989. Speciation and its ontology: The empirical consequences of alternative species concepts for understanding patterns and process of differentiation. In Otte, D. and J. A. Endler, ( eds ), Speciation and its Consequences. Sinauer, Sunderland, Massachusetts, pp. 28 – 59.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceCrother, B. L. 1990. Is “some better than none” or do allele frequencies contain phylogenetically useful information ? Cladistics 6: 277 – 281.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceDamuth, J. 1985. Selection among ‘species’: A formulation in terms of natural functional units. Evolution, 39: 1132 – 1146.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceDavis, J. I. and K. C. Nixon. 1992. Populations, variation, and the delimitaton of phylogenetic species. Syst. Biol., 41: 421 – 435.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceDonoghue, M. J. 1985. A critique of the biological species concept and recommendations for a phylogenetic alternative. Bryologist, 88: 172 – 181.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceFarris, J. S. 1976. An introduction to numerical classification (Review). Syst. Zool., 25: 92 – 95.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceFarris, J. S. 1983. The logical basis of phylogenetic analysis. In Platnick, N. I. and V. A. Funk, ( eds ), Advances in Cladistics, vol. 2. Columbia Univ. Press, New York, pp. 7 – 36.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceFitch, W. M. 1970. Distinguishing homologous from analogous proteins. Syst. Zool., 19: 99 – 113.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceFord, L. S. and D. C. Cannatella. 1993. The major clades of frogs. Herpetol. Monogr., 7: 94 – 117.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceFrost, D. R. and R. Etheridge. 1989. A phylogenetic analysis and taxonomy of iguanian lizards (Reptilia: Squamata). Misc. Publ. Mus. Nat. Hist. Univ. Kansas, 81: 1 – 65.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceFrost, D. R. and D. M. Hillis. 1990. Species in concept and practice: Herpetological considerations. Herpetoiogica, 46: 87 – 104.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceFrost, D. R. and J. W. Wright. 1988. The taxonomy of uniparental species, with special reference to parthenogenetic Cnemidophorus (Squamata: Teiidae). Syst. Zool., 37: 200 – 208.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceFrost, D. R., A. G. Kluge and D. M. Hillis. 1992. Species in contemporary herpetology: Comments on phylogenetic inference and taxonomy. Herpetol. Rev., 23: 46 – 54.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGaines, M. S., L. S. Mccleneghan, JR. and R. K. Rose. 1978. Temporal patterns of allozymic variation in fluctuating populations of Microtus ochrogaster. Evolution 32: 723 – 739.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGauthier, J. A. 1986. Saurischian monophyly and the origin of birds. In Padian, K., ( ed. ), The Origin of Birds and the Evolution of Flight. Mem. California Acad. Sci., 8: 1 – 55.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGauthier, J. A., R. Estes and K. de Queiroz. 1988. A phylogenetic analysis of Lepidosauromorpha. In Estes, R. and G. Pregill, ( eds ), Phylogenetic Relationships of Lizard Families: Essays Commemorating Charles L. Camp. Stanford Univ, Press, pp. 15 – 98.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGhiselin, M. 1966. On psychologism in the logic of taxonomic controversies. Syst. Zool., 15: 207 – 215.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGhiselin, M. 1974. A radical solution to the species problem. Syst. Zool., 23: 536 – 554.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGhiselin, M. 1981. Categories, life and thinking. Behav. Brain Sci. 4: 269 – 283, 303 – 313.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGhiselin, M. 1984. “Definition”, “character”, and other equivocal terms. Syst. Zool., 33: 104 – 110.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGhiselin, M. 1987. Species concepts, individuality, and objectivity. Biol. Philos., 2: 127 – 143.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGhiselin, M. 1988. The individuality thesis, essences, and the taws of nature. Biol. Philos, 3: 467 – 474.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGraybeal, A. 1995. Naming species. Syst. Biol. 44: in press.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGriffiths, G. C. D. 1974. On the foundations of biological systematics. Acta Bioth., 13: 85 – 131.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHempel, C. G. 1966. Philosophy of Natural Science. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHennig, W. 1966. Phylogenetic Systematics. Univ. Illinois Press, Urbana, Illinois.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHighton, R. 1989. Biochemical evolution in the slimy salamanders of the Plethodon glutinosus complex in the eastern United States. Part I. Geographic protein variation. Univ. Illinois Biol. Monogr., 57: 1 – 78.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHull, D. L. 1965. The effect of essentialism on taxonomy–Two thousand years of stasis (II). Br. J. Philos. Sci. 16 ( 61 ): 1 – 18.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHull, D. L. 1976. Are species really individuals ? Syst. Zool., 25: 174 – 191.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHull, D. L. 1977. The ontological status of species as evolutionary units. In Butts, R. and J. Hintikka, ( eds ), Foundational Problems in the Special Sciences. D. Reidel, Dordrecht-Holland, pp. 91 – 102.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHull, D. L. 1978. A matter of individuality. Philos. Sci., 45: 335 – 360.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHull, D. L. 1980. Individuality and selection. Annu. Rev. Ecol. Syst., 11: 311 – 332.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHull, D. L. 1981. Units of evolution; A metaphysical essay. In Jensen, U. L. and R. Harre, ( eds ), The Philosophy of Evolution. Harvester Press, Brighton, UK, pp. 23 – 44.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHull, D. L. 1983. Karl Popper and PlatO's Metaphor. In Platnick, N. I. and V. A. Funk, ( eds ), Advances in Cladistics. Proceedings of the second meeting of the Willi Hennig Society. Vol. 2. Columbia Univ. Press, New York, pp. 177 – 189.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHull, D. L. 1987. Genealogical actors in ecological roles. Biol. Philos., 2: 168 – 184.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKitcher, P. 1981. Explanatory unification. Philos. Sci. 48: 507–531. Reprinted in Boyd, R., P. Gasper and J. D. Trout, ( eds ), 1991, The Philosophy of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 329 – 347.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A. G. 1971. A quantitative approach to the biological species concept. Am. Philos. Yrbk.: 329 – 330.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A. G. 1983. Cladistics and the classification of the great apes. In Ciochon, R. L. and R. S. Corruccini, ( eds ), New Interpretation of Ape and Human Ancestry. Plenum Publ. Corp., New York, pp. 151 – 177.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A. G. 1985. Onotogeny and phylogenetic systematics. Cladistics, 1: 13 – 27.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A. G. 1988. Parsimony in vicariance: A quantitative method and a Greater Antillian example. Syst. Zool., 37: 315 – 328.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A. G. 1989. Metacladistics. Cladistics, 5: 291 – 294.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A. G. 1990. Species as historical individuals. Biol. Philos., 5: 417 – 431.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A. G. 1993. Three-taxon transformation and phylogenetic inference: Ambiguity and distortion as regards explanatory power. Cladistics, 9: 246 – 259.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKornet, D. 1993. Permanent splits as speciation events: A formal reconstruction of the internodal species concept. J. Theor. Biol., 164: 407 – 435.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceLiden, M. 1990. Replicators, hierarchy, and the species problem. Cladistics, 6: 183 – 186.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceLovtrup, S. 1979. The evolutionary species: Fact or fiction ? Syst. Zool., 28: 386 – 392.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMacarthur, R. 1972. Geographical Ecology: Patterns in the Distribution of Species. Harper & Row, Publishers, New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMayr, E. 1942. Systematics and the Origin of Species. Columbia Univ. Press, New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMayr, E. 1963. Animal Species and Evolution. Belknap Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMayr, E. 1969. Principles of Systematic Zoology. McGraw-Hill, Inc., New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMayr, E. 1976. Is the species a class or an individual ? Syst. Zool. 25: 192.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMayr, E. 1982. Of what use are subspecies ? Auk 99: 593 – 595.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMayr, E. 1987. The ontological status of species: Scientific progress and philosophical terminology. Biol. Philos., 2: 145 – 166.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMckitrick, M. C. 1994. On homology and the ontological relationship of parts. Syst. Biol., 43: 1 – 10.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMckitrick, M. C. and R. M. Zink. 1988. Species concepts in ornithology. Condor, 90: 1 – 14.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMindeli, D. R. 1991. Aligning DNA sequences: Homology and phylogenetic weighting. In Miyamoto, M. and J. Cracraft, ( eds ), Phylogenetic Analysis of DNA Sequences. Oxford Univ. Press, New York, pp. 73 – 89.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMishler, B. D. 1990. Species, speciation, and phytogenetic systematics. Cladistics, 6: 205 – 209.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMishler, B. D. and R. N. Brandon. 1987. Individuality, pluralism, and the phylogenetic species concept. Biol. Philos., 2: 397 – 414.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMishler, B. and M. Donoghue. 1982. Species concepts: A case for pluralism. Syst. Zool., 31: 491 – 503.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceNelson, G. 1978. Ontogeny, phylogeny, paleontology, and the biogenetic law. Syst. Zool., 27: 324 – 345.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceNelson, G. 1985. Class and individual: A reply to M. Ghiselin. Cladistics, 1: 386 – 389.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceNelson, G. 1989. Cladistics and evolutionary models. Cladistics, 5: 275 – 289.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceNelson, G. and N. I. Platnick. 1981. Systematics and Biogeography: Cladistics and Vicariance. Columbia Univ. Press, New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceNixon, K. C. and Q. D. Wheeler. 1990. An amplification of the phylogenetic species concept. Cladistics, 6: 211 – 223.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceNixon, K. C. and Q. D. Wheeler. 1992. Extinction and the origin of species. In Novacek, M. J. and Q. D. Wheeler, ( eds ), Extinction and Phylogeny. Columbia Univ. Press, New York, pp. 119 – 143.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceNorell, M. A. and K. de Queiroz. 1991. The earliest iguanine lizard (Reptilia: Squamata) and its bearing on iguanine phylogeny. Am. Mus. Novit., 2997: 1 – 16.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceO'Hara, R. J. 1993. Systematic generalization, historical fate, and the species problem. Syst. Biol. 42: 231 – 246.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceO'Neill, R. V., D. L. De Angelis, J. B. Wade and T. F. H. Allen. 1986. A hierarchical concept of ecosystems. Monogr. Pop. Biol. 23, Princeton Univ. Press, Princeton, New Jersey.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePanchen, A. L. 1992. Classification, Evolution and the Nature of Biology. Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, UK.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePatterson, C. 1982. Morphological characters and homology. In Joysey, K. A. and A. E. Friday, ( eds ), Problems of Phylogenetic Reconstruction, Academic Press, London, pp. 21 – 74.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePatterson, C. 1988. The impact of evolutionary theories on systematics. In Hawksworth, D. L., ( ed. ), Prospects in Systematics. Academic Press, London, pp. 59 – 91.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePatton. J. L. and M. F. Smith. 1994. Paraphyly, polyphyly, and the nature of species boundaries in pocket gophers (genus Thomomys). Syst. Biol., 43: 11 – 26.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencede Pinna, M. C C. 1991. Concepts and tests of homology in the cladistic paradigm. Cladistics, 7: 367 – 394.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePlatnick, N. I. 1979. Philosophy and the transformation of cladistics. Syst. Zool., 28: 537 – 546.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePlatnick, N. I. and E. S. Gaffney. 1977. Systematics: A Popperian perspective. Syst. Zool., 26: 360 – 366.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePlatnick, N. I. and E. S. Gatfney. 1978. Systematics and the Popperian paradigm. Syst. Zool., 27: 381 – 388.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePopper, K. R. 1957. The Poverty of Historicism. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, [ pages cited follow 1964 edition. Harper & Row, Publishers, New York. ].en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePopper, K. R. 1972. Conjectures and Refutations. The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. 4th ed. ( revised. Routledge ), New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePopper, K. R. 1979. Objective Knowledge. An Evolutionary Approach. Revised ed. Clarendon Press, Oxford Univ. Press, Oxford.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePopper, K. R. 1980. Evolution. New Scientist 87: 611.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePutnam, H. 1973. Explanation and reference. In Pearce, G. and P. Maynard, ( eds ), Conceptual Change, Kluwer Acad. Publ., Dordrecht. Reprinted in Boyd, R., P. Gasper and J. D. Trout (eds), 1991, The Philosophy of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 171–185.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePutnam, H. 1974. The ‘corroboration’ of theories. In Schilpp, P. A., ( ed. ), The Philosophy of Karl Popper. Open Court Publishing Company, LaSalle, Illinois, pp. 221 – 240. Reprinted in Boyd, R., P. Gasper and J. D. Trout (eds), 1991, The Philosophy of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 121–137.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencede Queiroz, K. 1985. The ontogenic method for determining character polarity and its relevance to phylogenetic systematics. Syst. Zool., 34: 280 – 299.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencede Queiroz, K. 1992. Phylogenetic definitions and taxonomic philosophy. Biol. Philos., 7: 295 – 313.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencede Queiroz, K. and M. J. Donoghue. 1988. Phylogenetic systematics and the species problem. Cladistics, 4: 317 – 338.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencede Queiroz, K. and M. J. Donoghue. 1990a. Phylogenetic systematics or Nelson's version of cladistics ? Cladistics, 6: 61 – 75.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencede Queiroz, K. and M. J. Donoghue. 1990b. Phylogenetic systematics and species revisited. Cladistics, 6: 83 – 90.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceRieppel, O. 1980. Homology–a deductive concept ? Z. Zool. Syst. Evolutionsforsch., 27: 193 – 199.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceRieppel, O. 1988. Fundamentals of Comparative Biology. Birkhauser, Basel, Switzerland.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceRieppel, O. 1990. Ontogeny–A way forward for systematics, a way backward for phylogeny. Biol. J. Linn. Soc., 39: 177 – 191.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceRieppel, O. 1991. Things, taxa and relationships. Cladistics, 7: 93 – 100.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceRieppel, O. 1992. Homology and logical fallacy. J. Evol. Biol., 5: 701 – 715.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceRosenberg, A. 1987. Why does the nature of species matter? Comments on Ghiselin and Mayr. Biol. Philos., 2: 192 – 197.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceRuse, M. 1979. Falsifiability, consilience, and systematics. Syst. Zool., 29: 530 – 536.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSalt, G. W. 1979. A comment on the use of the term emergent properties. Am. Nat., 113: 145 – 148.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSalthe, S. N. 1985. Evolving Hierarchical Systems. Columbia Univ. Press, New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSalthe, S. N. 1988. Notes toward a formal history of the levels concept. In Greenberg, G. and E. Torbach, ( eds ), Evolution of Social Behavior and Integrative levels. Lawrence Ehrlbaum Assoc, Hillsdale, New Jersey, pp. 53 – 64.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSalthe, S. N. 1989. Self-organization of/in hierarchically structured systems. Systems Res., 6: 199 – 208.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSalthe, S. N. 1991. Two forms of hierarchy theory in western discourses. Int. J. General Systems, 18: 251 – 264.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSneath, P. H. A. 1962. The construction of taxonomic groups. In Ainsworth, G. C. and P. H. A. Sneath, ( eds ), Microbial Classification, 12th Symposium of the Society for General Microbiology. Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, pp. 289 – 332.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSober, E. 1984. The Nature of Selection. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSober, E. 1988. Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSober, E. 1993. Philosophy of Biology. Dimensions of Philosophy Series, Westview Press, Boulder, Colorado.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSober, E. and R. Lewontin. 1982. Artifact, cause, and genie selection. Philos. Sci., 49: 157 – 180.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSokal, R. 1972. The species problem reconsidered. Syst. Zool., 22: 360 – 374.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSokal, R. and T. J. Crovello. 1970. The biological species concept: A critical evaluation. Am. Nat., 104: 127 – 153.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceStanley, S. M. 1975. A theory of evolution above the species level. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci., 72: 646 – 650.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceStanley, S. M. 1979. Macroevolution: Pattern and Process. Freeman, San Francisco.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceVan Valen, L. 1976. Individualistic classes. Philos. Sci., 43: 539 – 541.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceVrana, P. and W. Wheeler. 1992. Individual organisms as terminal entities: Laying the species problem to rest. Cladistics, 8: 67 – 72.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceVrba, E. S. and N. Eldredge. 1984. Individuals, hierarchies and processes: Towards a more complete evolutionary theory. Paleobiology, 10: 146 – 171.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWheeler, Q. D. and K. C. Nixon. 1990. Another way of looking at the species problem: A reply to de Queiroz and Donoghue. Cladistics, 6: 77 – 81.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWhittaker, R. H. 1969. Evolution of diversity in plant communities. In Diversity and Stability in Ecological Systems. Brookhaven Symp. Biol., 22: 178 – 196.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWiley, E. O. 1978. The evolutionary species concept reconsidered. Syst. Zool., 27: 88 – 92.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWiley, E. O. 1980. Is the evolutionary species fictiony–A consideration of classes, individuals, and historical entities. Syst. Zool., 29: 76 – 80.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWiley, E. O. 1981a. The metaphysics of individuality and its consequences for systematic biology. Behav. Brain Sci., 4: 302 – 303.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWiley, E. O. 1981b. Phylogenetics. The Theory and Practice of Phylogenetic Systematics. Wiley, New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWilkinson, M. 1994. Common cladistic information and its consensus representation: Reduced Adams and reduced consensus trees and profiles. Syst. Biol., 43: 343 – 368.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWilliams, M. B. 1985. Species are individuals: Theoretical foundations for the claim. Philos. Sci., 52: 578 – 590.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWilliams, M. B. 1989. Evolvers arc individuals: Extension of the species as individuals claim. In Ruse, M., ( ed. ), What the Philosophy of Biology Is: Essays for David Hull. Kluwer Acad. Publ., Amsterdam, pp. 305 – 312.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWilliams, M. B. 1992. Species: Current Usages. In Keller, E. F. and E. A. Lloyd, ( eds ), Keywords in Evolutionary Biology. Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 318 – 323.en_US
dc.owningcollnameInterdisciplinary and Peer-Reviewed


Files in this item

Show simple item record

Remediation of Harmful Language

The University of Michigan Library aims to describe library materials in a way that respects the people and communities who create, use, and are represented in our collections. Report harmful or offensive language in catalog records, finding aids, or elsewhere in our collections anonymously through our metadata feedback form. More information at Remediation of Harmful Language.

Accessibility

If you are unable to use this file in its current format, please select the Contact Us link and we can modify it to make it more accessible to you.