A CONSIDERATION OF EPISTEMOLOGY IN SYSTEMATIC BIOLOGY, WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO SPECIES
dc.contributor.author | Frost, Darrel R. | en_US |
dc.contributor.author | Kluge, Arnold G. | en_US |
dc.date.accessioned | 2010-06-01T20:34:31Z | |
dc.date.available | 2010-06-01T20:34:31Z | |
dc.date.issued | 1994-09 | en_US |
dc.identifier.citation | Frost, Darrel R.; Kluge, Arnold G. (1994). "A CONSIDERATION OF EPISTEMOLOGY IN SYSTEMATIC BIOLOGY, WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO SPECIES." Cladistics 10(3): 259-294. <http://hdl.handle.net/2027.42/73683> | en_US |
dc.identifier.issn | 0748-3007 | en_US |
dc.identifier.issn | 1096-0031 | en_US |
dc.identifier.uri | https://hdl.handle.net/2027.42/73683 | |
dc.description.abstract | Science progresses through the development of integrative theories that unify more and more subsidiary theories. Progress in phylogenetic theory comes from mutual reconciliation with the theoretical structure of other branches of evolutionary biology, such as developmental biology, population biology, and population genetics. The notions of species, individuality, and scalar hierarchy are keys to this reconciliation. Conflation of the results and simplifying assumptions of particular discovery operations with the nature of the entities that we search for is a continuing problem in inferential biology. Other problems extend from the fact that scientific discovery operations address sets of entities and sets of interactions, even when the definitions employed by the operations are not rigorous set-definers, but rather generalized descriptive approximations which summarize similarities among the parts of hierarchically more general entities. As an example, in the discovery methods of phylogenetic systematics, organisms (parts of species) are treated as if they are extensions of a set (the lineage considered as a set), rather than as indefinable parts of a particular (the lineage as a system). This simplifying assumption constitutes treating scalar hierarchies as if they are specification hierarchies and, although this may be necessary for scientific progress, it can lead to over-reductionism if applied uncritically. We expect all analytical techniques to fail at some frequency in part because the limits and reality of the entities that scientists attempt to discover do not extend from definitions used in discovery operations, For this reason, all operational definitions in systematics must be patched by theoretical (= process) claims to one degree or another to give us a more complete representation of evolutionary history. In our view, ontology is the result of reconciliation of theoretical expectations and lines of operational evidence (both of “direct” observation and logical techniques). This “consilience of inductions” provides a general picture of the world and illuminates the limitations of particular discovery operations. As our understanding of the lawful nature of the universe improves, we are able to refine the definitions used by our discovery operations. Against the backdrop of the payoffs to evolutionary biology, the various definitions of species are most starkly compared. In cases where tokogeny is not inherently hierarchical, the level of organization chosen as the basic unit that maximizes the explanatory power of phylogenetic hypotheses is the level of Evolutionary Species, which is that of largest integrating lineages, rather than the level of individual organisms. Nevertheless, we recognize that our discovery operations rest on observations of organismal characteristics. The Phylogenetic Species Concept is, at best, the operational equivalent of Evolutionary Species, but may identify parts of Evolutionary Species that are only temporarily isolated. The cost of this kind of error is judged to be small compared with the alternative of recognizing paraphyletic “species” on the basis of potential to recombine. Metaphyly, concerns about exclusiveness of lineages as something more than an analytical issue, and “an escape from species” through operationalism are judged to stem from errors of overreduction. | en_US |
dc.format.extent | 1737612 bytes | |
dc.format.extent | 3109 bytes | |
dc.format.mimetype | application/pdf | |
dc.format.mimetype | text/plain | |
dc.publisher | Blackwell Publishing Ltd | en_US |
dc.rights | 1994 The Willi Hennig Society | en_US |
dc.title | A CONSIDERATION OF EPISTEMOLOGY IN SYSTEMATIC BIOLOGY, WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO SPECIES | en_US |
dc.type | Article | en_US |
dc.subject.hlbsecondlevel | Ecology and Evolutionary Biology | en_US |
dc.subject.hlbtoplevel | Science | en_US |
dc.description.peerreviewed | Peer Reviewed | en_US |
dc.contributor.affiliationum | Curator, Museum of Zoology, and Professor, Department of Biology, The University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan 48109, U.S.A. | en_US |
dc.contributor.affiliationother | Assistant Curator, Department of Herpetology and Ichthyology, American Museum of Natural History, Central Park West at 79th Street, New York, New York 10024, U.S.A. | en_US |
dc.description.bitstreamurl | http://deepblue.lib.umich.edu/bitstream/2027.42/73683/1/j.1096-0031.1994.tb00178.x.pdf | |
dc.identifier.doi | 10.1111/j.1096-0031.1994.tb00178.x | en_US |
dc.identifier.source | Cladistics | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Ackery, P. R. and R. I. Vane-Wright. 1984. Milkweed Butterflies: Their Cladistics and Biology. Cornell Univ. Press, Ithaca, New York. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Alberch, P. 1985. Problems with the interpretation of developmental sequences. Syst. Zool., 34: 46 – 58. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Allard, M. W. and R. L. Honeycutt. 1991. Ribosomal DNA variation within and between species of rodents, with emphasis on the genus Onychomys. Mol. Biol. Evol., 8: 71 – 84. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Archibald, J. D. 1944. Metataxon concepts and assessing possible ancestry using phylogenetic systematics. Syst. Biol., 43: 27 – 40. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Arnold, E. N. 1981. Estimating phytogenies at low taxonomic levels. Z. Zool. Syst. Evolutionsforsch. 19: 1 – 35. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Avise, J. C. and R. M. Ball. 1990. Principles of genealogical concordance in species concepts and biological taxonomy. Oxford Surv. Evol. Biol., 7: 45 – 67. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Ax, P. 1985. Stem species and the stem lineage concept. Cladistics, 1: 279 – 287. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Barrett, M., M. J. Donogkue and E. Sober. 1991. Against consensus. Syst. Zool., 40: 486 – 493. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Baum, D. 1992. Phylogenetic species concepts. Trends Ecol. Evol., 7: 1 – 2. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Baum, D. and K. L. Shaw. 1995. Exclusivity, coalescence and the genealogical species. In P. C. Hoch, A. G. Stevenson and B. A. Schaal, ( eds ), Experimental and molecular approaches to plant biosystematics. Monogr. Syst., Missouri Botanical Garden, St. Louis, In press. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Baverstock, P. R., C. H. S. Watts and S. R. Cole. 1977. Electrophoretic comparisons between allopatric populations of five Australian pseudomyine rodents (Muridae). Aust. J. Biol. Sci., 30: 471 – 485. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Boyd, R. 1991. Confirmation, semantics, and the interpretation of scientific theories: Introductory essay. In Boyd, R., P. Gasper and J. D. Trout ( eds ). The Philosophy of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 3 – 35. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Boyd, R., P. Gasper and J. D. Trout ( eds ). 1991. The Philosophy of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Brady, R. H. 1983. Parsimony, hierarchy, and biological implications. In Platnick, N. I. and V. A. Funk, ( eds ), Advances in Cladistics, vol. 2. Columbia Univ. Press, New York, pp. 49 – 60. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Brooks, D. R. and E. O. Wiley. 1985. Theories and methods in different approaches to phylogenetic systematics. Cladistics, 1: 1 – 11. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Brooks, D. R. and E. O. Wiley. 1986. Evolution as Entropy: Toward a Unified Theory of Biology. Univ. Chicago Press, Chicago, Illinois. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Buck, R. C. and D. L. Hull. 1966. The logical structure of the Linnaean hierarchy. Syst. Zool. 15: 97 – 111. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Butts, R. E. ( ed. ). 1989. William Whewell's theory of scientific method. Revised edition. Hackett Publ. Co., Inc., Indianapolis. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Campbell. J. A. and D. R. Frost. 1993. Anguid lizards of the genus Abronia: Revisionary notes, descriptions of four new species, a phylogenetic analysis, and key. Ball. Am. Mus. Nat. Hist., 216: 1 – 121. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Carnap, R. 1956. Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. In Meaning and Necessity. Univ. Chicago Press. Reprinted in Boyd, R., P. Gasper and J. D. Trout, (eds), 1991, The Philosophy of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 85–97. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Cracraft, J. 1983. Species concepts and speciation analysis. Current Ornithol., 1: 159 – 187. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Cracraft J. 1987. Species concepts and the ontology of evolution. Biol. Philos., 2: 329 – 346. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Cracraft, J. 1989. Speciation and its ontology: The empirical consequences of alternative species concepts for understanding patterns and process of differentiation. In Otte, D. and J. A. Endler, ( eds ), Speciation and its Consequences. Sinauer, Sunderland, Massachusetts, pp. 28 – 59. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Crother, B. L. 1990. Is “some better than none” or do allele frequencies contain phylogenetically useful information ? Cladistics 6: 277 – 281. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Damuth, J. 1985. Selection among ‘species’: A formulation in terms of natural functional units. Evolution, 39: 1132 – 1146. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Davis, J. I. and K. C. Nixon. 1992. Populations, variation, and the delimitaton of phylogenetic species. Syst. Biol., 41: 421 – 435. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Donoghue, M. J. 1985. A critique of the biological species concept and recommendations for a phylogenetic alternative. Bryologist, 88: 172 – 181. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Farris, J. S. 1976. An introduction to numerical classification (Review). Syst. Zool., 25: 92 – 95. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Farris, J. S. 1983. The logical basis of phylogenetic analysis. In Platnick, N. I. and V. A. Funk, ( eds ), Advances in Cladistics, vol. 2. Columbia Univ. Press, New York, pp. 7 – 36. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Fitch, W. M. 1970. Distinguishing homologous from analogous proteins. Syst. Zool., 19: 99 – 113. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Ford, L. S. and D. C. Cannatella. 1993. The major clades of frogs. Herpetol. Monogr., 7: 94 – 117. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Frost, D. R. and R. Etheridge. 1989. A phylogenetic analysis and taxonomy of iguanian lizards (Reptilia: Squamata). Misc. Publ. Mus. Nat. Hist. Univ. Kansas, 81: 1 – 65. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Frost, D. R. and D. M. Hillis. 1990. Species in concept and practice: Herpetological considerations. Herpetoiogica, 46: 87 – 104. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Frost, D. R. and J. W. Wright. 1988. The taxonomy of uniparental species, with special reference to parthenogenetic Cnemidophorus (Squamata: Teiidae). Syst. Zool., 37: 200 – 208. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Frost, D. R., A. G. Kluge and D. M. Hillis. 1992. Species in contemporary herpetology: Comments on phylogenetic inference and taxonomy. Herpetol. Rev., 23: 46 – 54. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Gaines, M. S., L. S. Mccleneghan, JR. and R. K. Rose. 1978. Temporal patterns of allozymic variation in fluctuating populations of Microtus ochrogaster. Evolution 32: 723 – 739. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Gauthier, J. A. 1986. Saurischian monophyly and the origin of birds. In Padian, K., ( ed. ), The Origin of Birds and the Evolution of Flight. Mem. California Acad. Sci., 8: 1 – 55. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Gauthier, J. A., R. Estes and K. de Queiroz. 1988. A phylogenetic analysis of Lepidosauromorpha. In Estes, R. and G. Pregill, ( eds ), Phylogenetic Relationships of Lizard Families: Essays Commemorating Charles L. Camp. Stanford Univ, Press, pp. 15 – 98. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Ghiselin, M. 1966. On psychologism in the logic of taxonomic controversies. Syst. Zool., 15: 207 – 215. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Ghiselin, M. 1974. A radical solution to the species problem. Syst. Zool., 23: 536 – 554. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Ghiselin, M. 1981. Categories, life and thinking. Behav. Brain Sci. 4: 269 – 283, 303 – 313. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Ghiselin, M. 1984. “Definition”, “character”, and other equivocal terms. Syst. Zool., 33: 104 – 110. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Ghiselin, M. 1987. Species concepts, individuality, and objectivity. Biol. Philos., 2: 127 – 143. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Ghiselin, M. 1988. The individuality thesis, essences, and the taws of nature. Biol. Philos, 3: 467 – 474. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Graybeal, A. 1995. Naming species. Syst. Biol. 44: in press. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Griffiths, G. C. D. 1974. On the foundations of biological systematics. Acta Bioth., 13: 85 – 131. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Hempel, C. G. 1966. Philosophy of Natural Science. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Hennig, W. 1966. Phylogenetic Systematics. Univ. Illinois Press, Urbana, Illinois. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Highton, R. 1989. Biochemical evolution in the slimy salamanders of the Plethodon glutinosus complex in the eastern United States. Part I. Geographic protein variation. Univ. Illinois Biol. Monogr., 57: 1 – 78. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Hull, D. L. 1965. The effect of essentialism on taxonomy–Two thousand years of stasis (II). Br. J. Philos. Sci. 16 ( 61 ): 1 – 18. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Hull, D. L. 1976. Are species really individuals ? Syst. Zool., 25: 174 – 191. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Hull, D. L. 1977. The ontological status of species as evolutionary units. In Butts, R. and J. Hintikka, ( eds ), Foundational Problems in the Special Sciences. D. Reidel, Dordrecht-Holland, pp. 91 – 102. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Hull, D. L. 1978. A matter of individuality. Philos. Sci., 45: 335 – 360. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Hull, D. L. 1980. Individuality and selection. Annu. Rev. Ecol. Syst., 11: 311 – 332. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Hull, D. L. 1981. Units of evolution; A metaphysical essay. In Jensen, U. L. and R. Harre, ( eds ), The Philosophy of Evolution. Harvester Press, Brighton, UK, pp. 23 – 44. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Hull, D. L. 1983. Karl Popper and PlatO's Metaphor. In Platnick, N. I. and V. A. Funk, ( eds ), Advances in Cladistics. Proceedings of the second meeting of the Willi Hennig Society. Vol. 2. Columbia Univ. Press, New York, pp. 177 – 189. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Hull, D. L. 1987. Genealogical actors in ecological roles. Biol. Philos., 2: 168 – 184. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Kitcher, P. 1981. Explanatory unification. Philos. Sci. 48: 507–531. Reprinted in Boyd, R., P. Gasper and J. D. Trout, ( eds ), 1991, The Philosophy of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 329 – 347. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Kluge, A. G. 1971. A quantitative approach to the biological species concept. Am. Philos. Yrbk.: 329 – 330. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Kluge, A. G. 1983. Cladistics and the classification of the great apes. In Ciochon, R. L. and R. S. Corruccini, ( eds ), New Interpretation of Ape and Human Ancestry. Plenum Publ. Corp., New York, pp. 151 – 177. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Kluge, A. G. 1985. Onotogeny and phylogenetic systematics. Cladistics, 1: 13 – 27. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Kluge, A. G. 1988. Parsimony in vicariance: A quantitative method and a Greater Antillian example. Syst. Zool., 37: 315 – 328. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Kluge, A. G. 1989. Metacladistics. Cladistics, 5: 291 – 294. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Kluge, A. G. 1990. Species as historical individuals. Biol. Philos., 5: 417 – 431. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Kluge, A. G. 1993. Three-taxon transformation and phylogenetic inference: Ambiguity and distortion as regards explanatory power. Cladistics, 9: 246 – 259. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Kornet, D. 1993. Permanent splits as speciation events: A formal reconstruction of the internodal species concept. J. Theor. Biol., 164: 407 – 435. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Liden, M. 1990. Replicators, hierarchy, and the species problem. Cladistics, 6: 183 – 186. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Lovtrup, S. 1979. The evolutionary species: Fact or fiction ? Syst. Zool., 28: 386 – 392. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Macarthur, R. 1972. Geographical Ecology: Patterns in the Distribution of Species. Harper & Row, Publishers, New York. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Mayr, E. 1942. Systematics and the Origin of Species. Columbia Univ. Press, New York. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Mayr, E. 1963. Animal Species and Evolution. Belknap Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Mayr, E. 1969. Principles of Systematic Zoology. McGraw-Hill, Inc., New York. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Mayr, E. 1976. Is the species a class or an individual ? Syst. Zool. 25: 192. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Mayr, E. 1982. Of what use are subspecies ? Auk 99: 593 – 595. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Mayr, E. 1987. The ontological status of species: Scientific progress and philosophical terminology. Biol. Philos., 2: 145 – 166. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Mckitrick, M. C. 1994. On homology and the ontological relationship of parts. Syst. Biol., 43: 1 – 10. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Mckitrick, M. C. and R. M. Zink. 1988. Species concepts in ornithology. Condor, 90: 1 – 14. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Mindeli, D. R. 1991. Aligning DNA sequences: Homology and phylogenetic weighting. In Miyamoto, M. and J. Cracraft, ( eds ), Phylogenetic Analysis of DNA Sequences. Oxford Univ. Press, New York, pp. 73 – 89. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Mishler, B. D. 1990. Species, speciation, and phytogenetic systematics. Cladistics, 6: 205 – 209. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Mishler, B. D. and R. N. Brandon. 1987. Individuality, pluralism, and the phylogenetic species concept. Biol. Philos., 2: 397 – 414. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Mishler, B. and M. Donoghue. 1982. Species concepts: A case for pluralism. Syst. Zool., 31: 491 – 503. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Nelson, G. 1978. Ontogeny, phylogeny, paleontology, and the biogenetic law. Syst. Zool., 27: 324 – 345. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Nelson, G. 1985. Class and individual: A reply to M. Ghiselin. Cladistics, 1: 386 – 389. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Nelson, G. 1989. Cladistics and evolutionary models. Cladistics, 5: 275 – 289. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Nelson, G. and N. I. Platnick. 1981. Systematics and Biogeography: Cladistics and Vicariance. Columbia Univ. Press, New York. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Nixon, K. C. and Q. D. Wheeler. 1990. An amplification of the phylogenetic species concept. Cladistics, 6: 211 – 223. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Nixon, K. C. and Q. D. Wheeler. 1992. Extinction and the origin of species. In Novacek, M. J. and Q. D. Wheeler, ( eds ), Extinction and Phylogeny. Columbia Univ. Press, New York, pp. 119 – 143. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Norell, M. A. and K. de Queiroz. 1991. The earliest iguanine lizard (Reptilia: Squamata) and its bearing on iguanine phylogeny. Am. Mus. Novit., 2997: 1 – 16. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | O'Hara, R. J. 1993. Systematic generalization, historical fate, and the species problem. Syst. Biol. 42: 231 – 246. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | O'Neill, R. V., D. L. De Angelis, J. B. Wade and T. F. H. Allen. 1986. A hierarchical concept of ecosystems. Monogr. Pop. Biol. 23, Princeton Univ. Press, Princeton, New Jersey. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Panchen, A. L. 1992. Classification, Evolution and the Nature of Biology. Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, UK. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Patterson, C. 1982. Morphological characters and homology. In Joysey, K. A. and A. E. Friday, ( eds ), Problems of Phylogenetic Reconstruction, Academic Press, London, pp. 21 – 74. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Patterson, C. 1988. The impact of evolutionary theories on systematics. In Hawksworth, D. L., ( ed. ), Prospects in Systematics. Academic Press, London, pp. 59 – 91. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Patton. J. L. and M. F. Smith. 1994. Paraphyly, polyphyly, and the nature of species boundaries in pocket gophers (genus Thomomys). Syst. Biol., 43: 11 – 26. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | de Pinna, M. C C. 1991. Concepts and tests of homology in the cladistic paradigm. Cladistics, 7: 367 – 394. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Platnick, N. I. 1979. Philosophy and the transformation of cladistics. Syst. Zool., 28: 537 – 546. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Platnick, N. I. and E. S. Gaffney. 1977. Systematics: A Popperian perspective. Syst. Zool., 26: 360 – 366. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Platnick, N. I. and E. S. Gatfney. 1978. Systematics and the Popperian paradigm. Syst. Zool., 27: 381 – 388. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Popper, K. R. 1957. The Poverty of Historicism. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, [ pages cited follow 1964 edition. Harper & Row, Publishers, New York. ]. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Popper, K. R. 1972. Conjectures and Refutations. The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. 4th ed. ( revised. Routledge ), New York. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Popper, K. R. 1979. Objective Knowledge. An Evolutionary Approach. Revised ed. Clarendon Press, Oxford Univ. Press, Oxford. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Popper, K. R. 1980. Evolution. New Scientist 87: 611. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Putnam, H. 1973. Explanation and reference. In Pearce, G. and P. Maynard, ( eds ), Conceptual Change, Kluwer Acad. Publ., Dordrecht. Reprinted in Boyd, R., P. Gasper and J. D. Trout (eds), 1991, The Philosophy of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 171–185. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Putnam, H. 1974. The ‘corroboration’ of theories. In Schilpp, P. A., ( ed. ), The Philosophy of Karl Popper. Open Court Publishing Company, LaSalle, Illinois, pp. 221 – 240. Reprinted in Boyd, R., P. Gasper and J. D. Trout (eds), 1991, The Philosophy of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 121–137. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | de Queiroz, K. 1985. The ontogenic method for determining character polarity and its relevance to phylogenetic systematics. Syst. Zool., 34: 280 – 299. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | de Queiroz, K. 1992. Phylogenetic definitions and taxonomic philosophy. Biol. Philos., 7: 295 – 313. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | de Queiroz, K. and M. J. Donoghue. 1988. Phylogenetic systematics and the species problem. Cladistics, 4: 317 – 338. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | de Queiroz, K. and M. J. Donoghue. 1990a. Phylogenetic systematics or Nelson's version of cladistics ? Cladistics, 6: 61 – 75. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | de Queiroz, K. and M. J. Donoghue. 1990b. Phylogenetic systematics and species revisited. Cladistics, 6: 83 – 90. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Rieppel, O. 1980. Homology–a deductive concept ? Z. Zool. Syst. Evolutionsforsch., 27: 193 – 199. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Rieppel, O. 1988. Fundamentals of Comparative Biology. Birkhauser, Basel, Switzerland. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Rieppel, O. 1990. Ontogeny–A way forward for systematics, a way backward for phylogeny. Biol. J. Linn. Soc., 39: 177 – 191. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Rieppel, O. 1991. Things, taxa and relationships. Cladistics, 7: 93 – 100. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Rieppel, O. 1992. Homology and logical fallacy. J. Evol. Biol., 5: 701 – 715. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Rosenberg, A. 1987. Why does the nature of species matter? Comments on Ghiselin and Mayr. Biol. Philos., 2: 192 – 197. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Ruse, M. 1979. Falsifiability, consilience, and systematics. Syst. Zool., 29: 530 – 536. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Salt, G. W. 1979. A comment on the use of the term emergent properties. Am. Nat., 113: 145 – 148. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Salthe, S. N. 1985. Evolving Hierarchical Systems. Columbia Univ. Press, New York. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Salthe, S. N. 1988. Notes toward a formal history of the levels concept. In Greenberg, G. and E. Torbach, ( eds ), Evolution of Social Behavior and Integrative levels. Lawrence Ehrlbaum Assoc, Hillsdale, New Jersey, pp. 53 – 64. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Salthe, S. N. 1989. Self-organization of/in hierarchically structured systems. Systems Res., 6: 199 – 208. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Salthe, S. N. 1991. Two forms of hierarchy theory in western discourses. Int. J. General Systems, 18: 251 – 264. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Sneath, P. H. A. 1962. The construction of taxonomic groups. In Ainsworth, G. C. and P. H. A. Sneath, ( eds ), Microbial Classification, 12th Symposium of the Society for General Microbiology. Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, pp. 289 – 332. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Sober, E. 1984. The Nature of Selection. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Sober, E. 1988. Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Sober, E. 1993. Philosophy of Biology. Dimensions of Philosophy Series, Westview Press, Boulder, Colorado. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Sober, E. and R. Lewontin. 1982. Artifact, cause, and genie selection. Philos. Sci., 49: 157 – 180. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Sokal, R. 1972. The species problem reconsidered. Syst. Zool., 22: 360 – 374. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Sokal, R. and T. J. Crovello. 1970. The biological species concept: A critical evaluation. Am. Nat., 104: 127 – 153. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Stanley, S. M. 1975. A theory of evolution above the species level. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci., 72: 646 – 650. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Stanley, S. M. 1979. Macroevolution: Pattern and Process. Freeman, San Francisco. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Van Valen, L. 1976. Individualistic classes. Philos. Sci., 43: 539 – 541. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Vrana, P. and W. Wheeler. 1992. Individual organisms as terminal entities: Laying the species problem to rest. Cladistics, 8: 67 – 72. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Vrba, E. S. and N. Eldredge. 1984. Individuals, hierarchies and processes: Towards a more complete evolutionary theory. Paleobiology, 10: 146 – 171. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Wheeler, Q. D. and K. C. Nixon. 1990. Another way of looking at the species problem: A reply to de Queiroz and Donoghue. Cladistics, 6: 77 – 81. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Whittaker, R. H. 1969. Evolution of diversity in plant communities. In Diversity and Stability in Ecological Systems. Brookhaven Symp. Biol., 22: 178 – 196. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Wiley, E. O. 1978. The evolutionary species concept reconsidered. Syst. Zool., 27: 88 – 92. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Wiley, E. O. 1980. Is the evolutionary species fictiony–A consideration of classes, individuals, and historical entities. Syst. Zool., 29: 76 – 80. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Wiley, E. O. 1981a. The metaphysics of individuality and its consequences for systematic biology. Behav. Brain Sci., 4: 302 – 303. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Wiley, E. O. 1981b. Phylogenetics. The Theory and Practice of Phylogenetic Systematics. Wiley, New York. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Wilkinson, M. 1994. Common cladistic information and its consensus representation: Reduced Adams and reduced consensus trees and profiles. Syst. Biol., 43: 343 – 368. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Williams, M. B. 1985. Species are individuals: Theoretical foundations for the claim. Philos. Sci., 52: 578 – 590. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Williams, M. B. 1989. Evolvers arc individuals: Extension of the species as individuals claim. In Ruse, M., ( ed. ), What the Philosophy of Biology Is: Essays for David Hull. Kluwer Acad. Publ., Amsterdam, pp. 305 – 312. | en_US |
dc.identifier.citedreference | Williams, M. B. 1992. Species: Current Usages. In Keller, E. F. and E. A. Lloyd, ( eds ), Keywords in Evolutionary Biology. Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 318 – 323. | en_US |
dc.owningcollname | Interdisciplinary and Peer-Reviewed |
Files in this item
Remediation of Harmful Language
The University of Michigan Library aims to describe its collections in a way that respects the people and communities who create, use, and are represented in them. We encourage you to Contact Us anonymously if you encounter harmful or problematic language in catalog records or finding aids. More information about our policies and practices is available at Remediation of Harmful Language.
Accessibility
If you are unable to use this file in its current format, please select the Contact Us link and we can modify it to make it more accessible to you.