Show simple item record

Distinguishing “or” from “and” and the case for historical identification

dc.contributor.authorKluge, Arnold G.en_US
dc.date.accessioned2010-06-01T20:55:22Z
dc.date.available2010-06-01T20:55:22Z
dc.date.issued2002-12en_US
dc.identifier.citationKluge, Arnold G (2002). "Distinguishing “or” from “and” and the case for historical identification." Cladistics 18(6): 585-593. <http://hdl.handle.net/2027.42/74018>en_US
dc.identifier.issn0748-3007en_US
dc.identifier.issn1096-0031en_US
dc.identifier.urihttps://hdl.handle.net/2027.42/74018
dc.description.abstractThe adequacy of a probabilistic interpretation must be judged according to the nature of the event, or thing, being inferred. For example, conditional (frequency) probability is not admissible in the inference of phylogeny, because basic statements of common ancestry do not fulfill the requirements of the relations specified by the probability calculus. The probabilities of the situation peculiar to the time and place of origin of species are unique . Moreover, according to evolutionary theory, an event of species diversification is necessarily unique, because species are parts of a replicator continuum—species arise from ancestral species. Also, these probabilities cannot be ascertained , because the relevant situation cannot be repeated—it is unique. Finally, the applicability of conditional (frequency) probability is denied, because events of common ancestry have already occurred—there is nothing to predict. However, hypotheses of species relationships can be identified objectively according to the degree to which they have survived simultaneous testing with critical evidence, not with generally confirming evidence. The most parsimonious hypothesis of species relationships represents the least disconfirmed, best supported , proposition among the alternatives being compared. That hypothesis does not, however, deserve any special epistemological status beyond serving as the focus of the next round of testing.en_US
dc.format.extent134779 bytes
dc.format.extent3109 bytes
dc.format.mimetypeapplication/pdf
dc.format.mimetypetext/plain
dc.publisherBlackwell Publishing Ltden_US
dc.rights2002 The Willi Hennig Societyen_US
dc.titleDistinguishing “or” from “and” and the case for historical identificationen_US
dc.typeArticleen_US
dc.subject.hlbsecondlevelEcology and Evolutionary Biologyen_US
dc.subject.hlbtoplevelScienceen_US
dc.description.peerreviewedPeer Revieweden_US
dc.contributor.affiliationumMuseum of Zoology, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI 48109, USAen_US
dc.description.bitstreamurlhttp://deepblue.lib.umich.edu/bitstream/2027.42/74018/1/j.1096-0031.2002.tb00294.x.pdf
dc.identifier.doi10.1111/j.1096-0031.2002.tb00294.xen_US
dc.identifier.sourceCladisticsen_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBrady, R.H., 1985. On the independence of systematics. Cladistics 1, 113 – 126.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBrower, A.V.Z., 2002. Cladistics, phylogeny, evidence and explanation—A reply to Lee. Zool. Scr. 31, 221 – 223.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceBunge, M., 1998. Philosophy of Science: from Explanation to Justification, 2. Transaction Publishers, New Brunswick, NJ.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceCarpenter, J.M., 1992. Random cladistics. Cladistics 8, 147 – 153.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceDarwin, C., 1859. The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. Murray, London. [1964 facsimile of the first ed., Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA ].en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencede Quieroz, K., Poe, S., 2001. Philosophy and phylogenetic inference: a comparison of likelihood and parsimony methods in the context of Karl Popper's writings on corroboration. Syst. Biol. 50, 305 – 321.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceDobzhansky, T., 1973. Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. Am. Biol. Teacher 35, 125 – 129.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceElsasser, W., 1966. Atom and Organism. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceFarris, J.S., 1983. The logical basis of phylogenetic analysis. In: Platnick, N.I., Funk, V.A., ( Eds. ), Advances in Cladistics II. Columbia Univeristy Press, New York, pp. 7 – 36.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceFelsenstein, J., 1987. Comment [on Barry and Hartigan, 1987]. Stat. Sci. 2, 208 – 209.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceFelsenstein, J., 2001. The troubled growth of statistical phylogenetics. Syst. Biol. 50, 465 – 467.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceFelsenstein, J., 2002. Inferring Phylogenies. Sinauer, Sunderland, MA.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGhiselin, M.T., 1966. On psychologism in the logic of taxonomic controversies. Syst. Zool. 15, 207 – 215.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceGrant, T., 2002. Testing methods: the evaluation of discovery operations in evolutionary biology. Cladistics 18, 94 – 111.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHacking, I., 1965. Logic of Statistical Inference. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHacking, I., 2001. An Introduction to Probability and Inductive Logic. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHennig, W., 1966. Phylogenetic Systematics. University of Illinois Press, Urbana.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHowson, C., Urbach, P., 1993. Scientific Reasoning: the Bayesian Approach, second ed. Open Court, Chicago.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHuelsenbeck, J.P., Rannala, B., Masly, J.P., 2000. Accommodating phylogenetic uncertainty in evolutionary studies. Science 288, 2349 – 2350.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHuelsenbeck, J.P., Ronquist, F., Nielsen, R., Bollback, J.P., 2001a. Bayesian inference of phylogeny and its impact on evolutionary biology. Science 294, 2310 – 2314.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHuelsenbeck, J.P., Ronquist, F., Hall, B., 2001b. An introduction to Bayesian inference of phylogeny. [ http://morphbank.ebc.uu.se/mrbayes/manual.pdf ].en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHull, D.L., 1967. Certainty and circularity in evolutionary taxonomy. Evolution 21, 174 – 189.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHull, D.L., 1974. Philosophy of Biological Science. Prentice-Hall International, Englewood Cliffs, NJ.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHull, D.L., 1980. Individuality and selection. Annu. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 11, 311 – 332.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceHull, D.L., 1988. Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A.G., 1990. Species as historical individuals. Biol. Philos. 5, 417 – 431.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A.G., 1997a. Testability and the refutation and corroboration of cladistic hypotheses. Cladistics 13, 81 – 96.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A.G., 1997b. Sophisticated falsification and research cycles: consequences for differential character weighting in phylogenetic systematics. Zool. Scr. 26, 349 – 360.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A.G., 1998. Total evidence or taxonomic congruence: cladistics or consensus classification. Cladistics 14, 151 – 158.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A.G., 1999. The science of phylogenetic systematics: explanation, prediction, and test. Cladistics 15, 429 – 436.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceKluge, A.G., 2001. Philosophical conjectures and their refutation. Syst. Biol. 50, 322 – 330.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceLewontin, R.C., 1966. Is nature probable or capricious ? BioScience 16, 25 – 26.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceLidÉn, M., 1990. Replicators, hierarchy, and the species problem. Cladistics 6, 183 – 186.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceLosos, J.B., Jackman, T.R., Larson, A., de Queiroz, K., RodrÍquez-Schettino, L., 1998. Contingency and determinism in replicated adaptive radiations of island lizards. Science 279, 2115 – 2118.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceLynn, J., Harrell, F., Cohn, F., Wagner, D., Connors, A.F., 1997. Prognosis of seriously ill hospitalized patients on the days before death: implications for patient care and public policy. New Horizons 5, 56 – 61.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMindell, D.P., 1991. Similarity and congruence as criteria for molecular homology. Mol. Biol. Evol. 8, 897 – 900.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceMurphy, W.J., Eizirki, E., O'Brien, S.J., Madsen, O., Scally, M., Douady, C.J., Teeling, E., Ryder, O.A., Stanhope, M.J., de Jong, W.W., Springer, M.S., 2001. Resolution of the early placental mammal radiation using Bayesian phylogenetics. Science 294, 2348 – 2351.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePatterson, C., 1978. Verifiability in systematics. Syst. Zool. 27, 218 – 222.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePlatnick, N.I., 1982. Defining characters and evolutionary groups. Syst. Zool. 32, 282 – 284.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePopper, K., 1957. The Poverty of Historicism. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePopper, K., 1959. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Harper & Row, New York. [ 1968 edition ].en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePopper, K., 1979. Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford University Press, New York.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePopper, K., 1983. Realism and the Aim of Science. Routledge, London.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferencePopper, K., 1990. A World of Propensities. Thoemmes, Bristol.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceRailton, P., 1978. A deductive-nomological model of probabilistic explanation. Philos. Sci. 45, 206 – 226.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceRieppel, O., 2002a. Beyond the logic of scientific discovery: a theory of empirical classes. In: Biodiversity in the Information Age. Sixth International Congress of Systematic and Evolutionary Biology. University of Patras, Patras, Greece, p. 30 [ Abstract ].en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceRieppel, O., 2002b. The meaning of homology. In: Biodiversity in the Information Age. Sixth International Congress of Systematic and Evolutionary Biology. University of Patras, Patras, Greece, p. 195 [ Abstract ].en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSalmon, W.C., 1966. The Foundations of Scientific Inference. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSarkar, S., 1998. Genetics and Reductionism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSiddall, M.E., 2001. Philosophy and phylogenetic inference: a comparison of likelihood and parsimony methods in the context of Karl Popper's writings on corroboration. Cladistics 17, 395 – 399.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSiddall, M.E., Kluge, A.G., 1997. Probabilism and phylogenetic inference. Cladistics 13, 313 – 336.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSaber, E., 1988. Reconstructing the past: Parsimony, evolution, and inference. Bradford Book, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceStamos, D.N., 1996. Popper, falsifiability, and evolutionary biology. Biol. Philos. 11, 161 – 191.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceStamos, D.N., 2001. Quantum indeterminism and evolutionary biology. Philos. Sci. 68, 164 – 184.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceSytsma, K.J., Pires, J.C., 2001. Plant systematics in the next 50 years-Re-mapping the new frontier. Taxon 50, 713 – 732.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWalton, D.N., 1985. Are circular arguments necessarily vicious ? Am. Philos. Q. 22, 263 – 274.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWatkins, J.W.N., 1984. Science and Scepticism. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWenzel, J.W., Carpenter, J.M., 1994. Comparing methods: adaptive traits and tests of adaptation. In: Eggleton, P., Vane-Wright, R.I., ( Eds. ), Linnaean Society Symposium Series. Phylogenetics and Ecology, 17. Academic Press, London, pp. 79 – 101.en_US
dc.identifier.citedreferenceWiley, E.O., 1975. Karl R. Popper, systematics, and classification: a reply to Walter Bock and other evolutionary taxonomists. Syst. Zool. 24, 233 – 242.en_US
dc.owningcollnameInterdisciplinary and Peer-Reviewed


Files in this item

Show simple item record

Remediation of Harmful Language

The University of Michigan Library aims to describe library materials in a way that respects the people and communities who create, use, and are represented in our collections. Report harmful or offensive language in catalog records, finding aids, or elsewhere in our collections anonymously through our metadata feedback form. More information at Remediation of Harmful Language.

Accessibility

If you are unable to use this file in its current format, please select the Contact Us link and we can modify it to make it more accessible to you.